Hi there,
Australian bioethicist Rob Sparrow has written extensively on topics ranging from political philosophy and minority rights to the ethics of war. Yet he is best known for his work in bioethics.
As Richard R. Sharp has noted, “Sparrow’s scholarship exemplifies the value of the intellectual gadfly – even when that work ruffles a few feathers among the bioethical elite.”
In this exclusive interview Professor Sparrow and BioEdge’s Xavier Symons discuss genetic diversity, the elimination of disability, and the so-called new eugenics.
Click here to read it:
http://clicks.aweber.com/y/ct/
Cheers,
Michael Cook
Editor, BioEdge
BioEdge: bioethics news from around the world
New Media Foundation | Level 2, 5 George St | North Strathfield NSW 2137 | AUSTRALIA | +61 2 8005 8605
Diversity, disability and eugenics: an interview with Rob Sparrow
by Xavier Symons | 11 Aug 2016 | 1 comment
Australian bioethicist Rob Sparrow has written extensively on topics ranging from political philosophy and minority rights to the ethics of war, robot ethics and even the ethics of nanotechnology. Yet he is arguably best known for his work in bioethics. While in one sense part of a mainstream bioethics academy, Professor Sparrow often provides a refreshingly unique perspective and challenges establishment opinions in the field. As Richard R. Sharp has noted, “Sparrow’s scholarship exemplifies the value of the intellectual gadfly – even when that work ruffles a few feathers among the bioethical elite.”
In the following interview Professor Sparrow and BioEdge’s Xavier Symons discuss current controversies in bioethics and, in particular, questions surrounding genetic diversity, the elimination of disability, and the so-called new eugenics.
******
Vulnerability and genetic diversityXavier Symons: Recently you've written on the topic of disability and new reproductive technologies. This seems related to the notion of vulnerability as it has been discussed in recent philosophical literature.
Rob Sparrow: There is a debate about vulnerability, which is concerned with power relations –for example, between people doing medical research and their research subjects – and a debate about the sort of vulnerability to contingency that some people want to insist on as being a valuable part of the human condition. I’ve really only written on the second of these topics.
XS: Let’s focus on the second kind of vulnerability, then. Do you think considerations about the value of vulnerability should play a role in our bioethical policy on reproductive technologies?
RS: Certainly. One, typically philosophical, context in which to think about this is to consider what David Pearce calls the ‘abolitionist project’ – the transhumanist fantasy that we could use biotechnology to eliminate all suffering in all sentient creatures. You might well wonder whether this would be utopian or dystopian. Back in reality, we are arguably medicalising suffering through our accounts of depression. The idea that people have a right to be happy all the time has a certain cultural currency nowadays, such that it can be tempting to conclude that when people aren’t happy it represents a failure of society and/or of medicine. That’s another context in which you might wonder about the value of suffering.
Rob Sparrow
XS: Many people seem to have the intuition that overcoming challenges or adversity is somehow part and parcel of a fulfilled life.RS: I do think there’s something to this. It’s a powerful intuition that a life of uninterrupted bliss is in some sense shallower, less interesting, than a life that involves overcoming trials, or involves the sorts of human relationships that are predicated on vulnerability. One might think of caring relationships here; for instance, such as love or sympathy. Trust is another relationship that necessarily involves vulnerability. In trusting, we become vulnerable to betrayal and to suffering as a result of betrayal. I’m not sure I would want to live in a world wherein it were impossible to demonstrate trust.
XS: Yes, Martha Nussbaum deals with this idea in The Fragility of Goodness.
RS: Indeed. So there are lots of reasons why we should be suspicious of the idea that we should strive to eliminate all suffering. However, having said this, when it comes to the value of any particular instance of vulnerability or suffering we have to be careful about embracing a kind of fatalism, such that we have no reason to prevent these things. Accounts of the value of suffering in general risk becoming a kind of theodicy wherein we are committed to the claim that ours is the best of possible worlds.
"The idea that people have a right to be happy all the time has a certain cultural currency nowadays"
Moreover, when it comes to the suffering of future people, the idea that we should — on the basis of our intuitions about the value of vulnerability or suffering — chose to ensure that people are vulnerable seems problematic. I explored this idea in an article on imposing genetic diversity. When you really push hard on the idea that one might consciously choose to bring about a world in which there was more vulnerability or lower welfare for the sake of producing the value that supposedly flows from these things it starts to look rather mercenary.XS: Perhaps we can discuss the relationship between conservation of disability and imposition of disability. Many would have the intuition that there’s nothing wrong with conserving the way things are, and that, indeed, there might even be something good with retaining the existing diversity of human capacities, while still balking at the idea that we should impose disability.
RS: In heritage conservation you might want to preserve a building that you wouldn't necessarily chose to build now… so it’s clear that at least in some contexts, history does matter. Where I think that argument becomes less plausible is if you are using an argument about conservation to guide policies in relation to reproductive technologies. If we make choices now that will lead to people having less good lives in the future, for the sake of conserving features of the world we live in — such as diversity — that we think are important, I’m inclined to think that this would involve imposing a particular world on future people.
Disability culture
XS: Perhaps this is a good opportunity to discuss the idea of a ‘disability culture’. Some people may think that there is such a thing as ‘disability culture’, and that this culture is valuable and worth preserving. Does ‘disability culture’ count as a reason why we shouldn’t attempt to eliminate disability?
RS: If you can show that preventing the birth of individuals with particular disabilities would lead to the loss of a distinctive culture then that does seem to establish an ethical issue that can’t be settled straightforwardly by reference to the welfare of individuals. People typically have an intuition that cultures are valuable in their own right. Notice, though, that this intuition concerns the value of a good that can only be sustained by a collective, and may even only be good for a collective.
Now there are different ways in which you might think there is an association between particular forms of physical embodiment or sets of intellectual capacities, which we sometimes identify as disability, and culture.
To my mind the strongest case that can be made for a relationship between disability and a distinctive culture relates to “capital D” Deaf culture. In this case, what looks to most people like an impairment – being hard of hearing – is associated with a language, a signed language. In fact there are any number of unique signed languages sustained by Deaf people in different communities around the world. Thus the various medical technologies that are working to eliminate deafness — most notoriously the cochlear implant — are also leading to language extinction and thus cultural extinction.
"People typically have the intuition that cultures are valuable in their own right"
The idea that we might remove someone from their culture in order to give them more opportunities – which is one of the justifications for cochlear implantation – has a longer history in debates about the value of culture. In the Australian context, it’s tempting to place the ethics of cochlear implantation alongside the history of the “Stolen Generations”, in which indigenous children were stolen from their parents and placed in the homes of white couples. Of course, this policy was mostly motivated by racist and genocidal ideas… but it’s occasionally been defended in terms of providing indigenous children with greater opportunities than they would have had growing up in their own culture. In practice, it was usually at the expense of the welfare of the stolen children, at least in part because forced cultural assimilation usually fails. Even if it were successful though, we might wonder whether such a policy could ever be justified.However, what’s different about the Deaf case is that deaf children will usually be born to hearing parents, which makes the argument about cultural rights especially tricky and ultimately, I suspect, less convincing… Anyway, with Deaf culture you’ve got disability producing a distinct language so that the argument that it is associated with a distinct culture is incredibly strong.
People do occasionally suggest that there is such a thing as “disability culture”, associated not with any particular disability but rather with the experience of disability in general. I suspect that this claim is more plausible if formulated as a claim about distinctive experiences rather than a distinctive culture. Anyone who is committed to any kind of standpoint epistemology, for instance, should concede that people living with disabilities may have an important contribution to make on many different moral and political questions. Regardless, as someone who, for the most part, is identified as able-bodied, I’m not especially well-placed to rule on this question. What I would say is that if there is an association between disability and a distinct culture or cultures, that doesn’t settle the question of the ethics of prenatal testing…. even if it does complexify it.
Disability, abortion, and a life worth living
XS: One specific bioethical matter related to disability is the increasingly effective detection of Down syndrome via PGD, and the concomitant increase of abortion of children with Down syndrome. Do you think there is something problematic about this?
RS: Philosophers and the medical profession have been way too swift to make judgements about other people’s quality of life and the extent to which particular forms of embodiment are compatible with human flourishing and with making a valuable social contribution. So there is an urgent moral demand on bioethicists to take up the arguments that have been made by disability advocates about the ethics of policies of selective termination, genetic screening, PGD, and so forth. This doesn’t require that you reach the same conclusions, but it does require a serious project of listening and engagement. This is particularly challenging — but also important — because, for all sorts of reasons, the perspectives of people with disabilities, particularly cognitive ones, are not well represented in bioethics, nor are they well represented in the institutions that determine policy regarding these technologies.
XS: So you think there are deeper ethical questions that have been overlooked by the bioethical community?
RS: Yes. I believe that, at the very least, when thinking about the ethics of prenatal testing and selective abortion, we are required to ask some quite traditional philosophical questions, of the sort we were discussing earlier, about what makes a human life go well, the nature of human flourishing, and whether suffering, vulnerability or particularity need always be negatively correlated with flourishing.
"Philosophers and the medical profession have been way too swift to make judgements about other people’s quality of life"
One way of encouraging people working in philosophy and bioethics to take the arguments made by disability critics seriously is to ask them to imagine that people like them were being selectively terminated. In a number of publications, I’ve been exploring an argument wherein I’ve tried to show that the so-called “obligation” of procreative beneficence – the duty to have the best child possible –might require the selective termination of male embryos on the grounds that it is better to be born a woman. What’s been striking about the response to those papers is that all of a sudden the mostly male philosophers writing about human enhancement start channelling the disability community. They say things like ‘it’s not worse to be a man, it’s just different’ or “but there are good things about not being able to get pregnant.” Indeed, they start celebrating the value of diversity! People who have previously been insisting that there’s always an answer to whether it’s better to be hearing or deaf – that’s straight forward, it’s better to be hearing! – begin emphasising instead that there are many ways of flourishing as a human being, many different notions of what “the good” consists in! My hope is that if I can encourage bioethicists to feel the force of those intuitions when they are confronted with the possibility that people like themselves will not exist in the future, they might be willing to look again at arguments made by disability activists and take them more seriously.A new eugenics?
XS: There has been spirited discussion recently about reproductive ethics and the supposed moral imperative to try to have the healthiest and fittest children possible. Do you think the label ‘the new eugenics’ is a fair way to describe the project of Savulescu and others?
RS: I would be very surprised if Julian would object to that description. There’s any number of philosophers who have tried to distinguish between the historical eugenics programs that involved atrocious human rights abuses and the philosophical underpinnings of the project of trying to ensure that people are born with better genes. They often conclude that we should countenance a ‘new eugenics’, which would be voluntary, human-rights respecting, and based on good genetics…. as opposed to the old “race science” that was based on bogus scientific claims and endorsed restrictions on the reproductive liberty of couples — not to mention murder!
One of the things I’m grappling with in my work at the moment is how plausible it is to identify — as I have tended to in previous writing — the willingness to regulate decisions around reproduction so as to secure collective goods, at the expense of individual welfare, as one of the morally problematic features of the old eugenics. The existence of collective action problems and the potentially disastrous aggregate consequences of widespread selection in the absence of any restrictions on the uses of technologies of genetic selection seem to require us to put notions of public health and the good of society at the heart of any plausible system of regulation of reproductive technologies. Then I worry that the collective good will once again be used to justify restrictions on the reproductive liberty of individuals.
"I don't think we're as far from the history of the bad old eugenics as many bioethicists would like to think"
If some advocates of the new eugenics are to be believed, future developments in technologies of genetic human enhancement are going to make very large benefits available to both individuals and societies. It seems to me that, should this ever eventuate, it will render it plausible to argue not only that individuals who are not making the socially validated choices are doing the wrong thing , but that they should be incentivised to make the right choice, or even punished for, or prevented from, making the “wrong” choice. Still, today, we occasionally see the re-emergence of bigoted ideas about what constitutes “good genes” and who should be having children….. even of policies of forced sterilization. So I don’t think we’re as far from the history of the bad old eugenics as many bioethicists would like to think.The other danger with the contemporary philosophical enthusiasm for the new eugenics is that all the talk about the contribution that genes make to a good human life — about some people having “better genes” — may encourage a return to dubious “genetic” accounts of the origins of inequality. Responsible scholars will always emphasise that genes and environment work together and that you can’t simply read off someone’s genetics from their social status. However, there are all sorts of social and political forces at work today that encourage us to think that people who are essentially lucky, who become wealthy as result of a series of fortuitous circumstances that allowed them to succeed where other people with similar ambitions failed, must actually be geniuses… that there must be something in them rather than in the history that led to them being where they are that made them successful.
Then it’s an easy leap to the conclusion that, if this person is a genius — which they must be because they have billions of dollars — it is because of their genes. Perhaps more importantly, the same argument is run at the other end of the social spectrum such that some people will look at others who are in prison or are drug addicted or are socially marginal, and reach for a “genetic” explanation for why that’s the case. Even if new reproductive and/or genetic technologies never realise the potential that advocates of the new eugenics think they might have, the social and political consequences of the contemporary philosophical debate about them are reason to fear that the “new” eugenics cannot be entirely divorced from the shameful history of eugenics in the 20th century.
Diversity, disability and eugenics: An interview with Rob Sparrow
No hay comentarios:
Publicar un comentario