In defence of conscientious objection
by Xavier Symons | 10 Nov 2019 | 1 comment
A newly released edition of the journal Perspectives in Medicine and Biology focuses on the theme of conscience in healthcare, and seeks to provide a deeper analysis of how conscience relates to good medical practice. The themed issue of Perspectives comes in the wake of two other themed editions of major bioethics journals that criticised conscientious objection in medicine.
The editors of the special issue, Dr Farr Curlin (Duke University) and Dr Kevin Powell (a pediatrician based in St Louis), argue that debate on conscientious objection has failed to address deeper questions about the nature of medical practice and the role of conscience in professional life:
“The dialogue [on conscientious objection] has often been hindered by participants talking past one another, using contested terms in different ways without argument, and leaving unspoken the participants' premises regarding what medicine is for and how practicing conscientiously relates to good medicine”.
The essays in the issue seek to tackle some of these basic topics. The collection begins with a paper by Lauris Kaldjian (University of Iowa), which argues that the exercise of conscience is inseparable from ethics and from the practice of medicine. Kaldjian proposes that the public should grant physicians substantial latitude to refuse to participate in practices that the physician, in his or her “final and best assessment”, believes fall “outside the scope of healing”.
Abraham Nussbaum (University of Colorado Denver) challenges the language that portrays physicians as either loyal soldiers or conscientious objectors, and he explores two 20th-century examples in which dissent within psychiatry led to needed reform of the profession.
Farr Curlin and Christopher Tollefsen (University of South Carolina) argue that the conscientious refusals that have drawn attention are in fact refusals based on medical reasons—based on judgments about what good medicine requires and permits. They call for such refusals to be accommodated, even celebrated, and for physicians to refuse to cooperate in any intervention that contradicts the physician's commitment to the patient's health, no matter how legal and professionally permitted that intervention is.
While several themes are explored in the special issue of Perspectives, its greatest contribution lies in its robust exploration of the Hippocratic idea of a doctor as a healer, and a consideration of what this means for conscientious objection in medicine.
Xavier Symons is Deputy Editor of BioEdge
It sounds like the premise for a Stephen King novel, but it’s real life. Benjamin Schreiber, a 66-year-old man, is serving a life sentence for murder in an Iowa prison. Back in 1996, he bludgeoned a man to death with an axe handle. In 2015 he suddenly became seriously ill, so ill that he lapsed into a coma and “died”.
But he recovered. Disappointed that he was still alive, he appealed to have his life sentence voided as it had already “expired”.
It’s an intriguing argument. Can you live two lives? Are you the same person after being resuscitated? Or are you literally a dead man walking?
Unfortunately for Schreiber, the court took a dim view of his request.
“We do not find his argument persuasive,” wrote a judge this week. She concluded: “Schreiber is either still alive, in which case he must remain in prison, or he is actually dead, in which case this appeal is moot.”
This ruling will allow the citizens of Iowa to sleep easier at night, but philosophically isn’t a bit naive in the way it addresses the problem of identity? Isn’t it possible that Mr (1996) Schreiber is dead and that Mr (2019) Schreiber is a different person? If S(2019) identifies as a dead person, shouldn’t we accept his carefully considered opinion?
But he recovered. Disappointed that he was still alive, he appealed to have his life sentence voided as it had already “expired”.
It’s an intriguing argument. Can you live two lives? Are you the same person after being resuscitated? Or are you literally a dead man walking?
Unfortunately for Schreiber, the court took a dim view of his request.
“We do not find his argument persuasive,” wrote a judge this week. She concluded: “Schreiber is either still alive, in which case he must remain in prison, or he is actually dead, in which case this appeal is moot.”
This ruling will allow the citizens of Iowa to sleep easier at night, but philosophically isn’t a bit naive in the way it addresses the problem of identity? Isn’t it possible that Mr (1996) Schreiber is dead and that Mr (2019) Schreiber is a different person? If S(2019) identifies as a dead person, shouldn’t we accept his carefully considered opinion?
Michael Cook
Editor BioEdge |
NEWS THIS WEEK
by Michael Cook | Nov 10, 2019
Supporters of abortion welcomed the decision
by Michael Cook | Nov 10, 2019
First in the United States
by Michael Cook | Nov 10, 2019
What if the parents are drug addicts who effectively beat her to death?
by Michael Cook | Nov 10, 2019
We are in a crisis, say some scientists
by Michael Cook | Nov 10, 2019
Even 25 years after legalisation in Oregon
by Michael Cook | Nov 10, 2019
This interview gives a good insight into his theories
by Xavier Symons | Nov 10, 2019
IVF experts have criticised fertility clinics for marketing expensive additional therapies
by Xavier Symons | Nov 10, 2019
A leading ethics journal has published a feature issue on conscientious objection
BioEdge
Level 1, 488 Botany Road, Alexandria NSW 2015 Australia
Phone: +61 2 8005 8605
Mobile: 0422-691-615
No hay comentarios:
Publicar un comentario